Reflection of the concept "memory" in literature - Курсовая работа

бесплатно 0
4.5 48
The concept "memory" and stylistic devices as the objects of linguistic research. Memory and causal connectedness. Realization of the concept "memory" and peculiarities of use of lexical stylistic devices in the novel "Jane Eyre" by Charlotte Bronte.

Скачать работу Скачать уникальную работу

Чтобы скачать работу, Вы должны пройти проверку:


Аннотация к работе
The ontological implications of such terminological distinctions are disputed: there are substantive disagreements about whats meant by the notion of a memory system, and about the utility of ‘systems’ taxonomies [9]. Progress in understanding psychological kinds and systems more generally is required in order to settle these issues. The following general characterisations are accepted even by those who stress the interactive coordination of the various forms of remembering. Philosophers ‘habit memory’ is, roughly, psychologists ‘procedural memory’. These labels cover a range of phenomena, from simpler forms of associative learning through to kinesthetic, skill, and sequence memory. We naturally refer to procedural, habit, and skill memories with the grammatical construction ‘remembering how’. I continue to remember how to type, play piano, or dance, even when I am not, now, occurrently engaged in the relevant activity. While some habit memories may have something in common with rigid, inflexible, automated conditioning mechanisms, others are flexible and open to the changing influences of context, mood, and personal memory. But even richer, idiosyncratic memories for skills differ from other, more explicit forms of memory in their acquisition, nature, content, phenomenology, articulability, and patterns of breakdown. Alongside revived interest in the general problem of relations between knowing how and knowing that, the philosophy of kinesthetic memory and skilled movement can draw on applied fields including philosophy of sport, dance, and music [9]. ‘Propositional memory’ is ‘semantic memory’ or memory for facts, the vast network of conceptual information underlying our general knowledge of the world: this is naturally expressed as ‘remembering that’, for example, that Descartes died in Sweden. Recollective memory is ‘episodic memory’, also sometimes called ‘personal memory’, ‘experiential memory’, or ‘direct memory’ by philosophers: this is memory for experienced events and episodes, such as a conversation this morning or the death of a friend eight years ago. Episodic memories are naturally expressed with a direct object: I remember arguing about Descartes yesterday, and I remember my feelings as we talked. Such personal memories can be generic or specific, and can be memories of more or less extended temporal periods. But the most characteristic feature of episodic remembering, arguably, is the way it brings us into contact with the particular past events which such memories are about and by which they are caused. Both semantic and episodic memories, whether linguistically expressed or not, usually aim at truth, and are together sometimes called ‘declarative memory’, in contrast to nondeclarative forms of memory, which dont seem to represent the world or the past in the same sense. In declarative remembering, we seek to track the truth: this is why we are uneasy or dismayed when our take on the past is challenged or overturned. This contrast between declarative and nondeclarative memory is sometimes lined up with a more controversial distinction between ‘explicit’ and ‘implicit’ memory: explicit memories, roughly, can be accessed verbally or otherwise by the subject, whereas implicit memory is memory without awareness. But the category of implicit memory includes a range of heterogeneous phenomena, and it may be better to see ‘implicit memory’ as a label for a set of memory tasks rather than a distinct variety or system of memory. We sometimes use ‘remember’ in its declarative senses as a ‘success-word’, so that ‘false memories’ are not ‘memories’ at all. Its possible either to think that I remember when in fact I am imagining or confabulating, or to think that I am creating something quite new (such as a melody, painting, or story) when in fact I am remembering it.[10] Classification and explanation of the many varieties of false ‘memory’ are also intriguing philosophical tasks [11]; and the attempt to understand and explain any features, both phenomenological and causal, which veridical remembering and (some cases of) imagining, confabulating, and misremembering might have in common is a legitimate part of the overall interdisciplinary enquiry into memory. (Dickens) The object clause what can never be replaced is a periphrasis for the word mother. The concept is easily understood by the reader within the given context, the latter being the only code which makes the deci­phering of the phrase possible. This is sufficiently proved by a simple trans­formational operation, viz. taking the phrase out of its context. The mean­ing of what can never be replaced used independently will bear no refe­rence to the concept mother and may be interpreted in many ways. The periphrasis here expresses a very-individual idea of the concept. In some cases periphrasis is regarded as a demerit and should have no place in good, precise writing. This kind of periphrasis is generally called circumlocution. Thus Richard Alti

Вы можете ЗАГРУЗИТЬ и ПОВЫСИТЬ уникальность
своей работы


Новые загруженные работы

Дисциплины научных работ





Хотите, перезвоним вам?